ࡱ> ( F/ 0|DArialasRomanPP,EؖO 0ؖ"DTimes New RomanPP,EؖO 0ؖ DWingdingsRomanPP,EؖO 0ؖ0DSymbolgsRomanPP,EؖO 0ؖ@DVerdanasRomanPP,EؖO 0ؖ" A . @n?" dd@  @@`` X$w!....   21   21)*+234569:;<=>?@>>   21   () 5    ()v wyz{|}~ 0AA@8WX:m ʚ;6_v8ʚ;g4PdPd O 0ppp@ <4ddddv 0PE<4!d!dv 0PE f0___PPT10 pp&___PPT9  * , #, ?  %(How many choices can a libertarian make? ) NFilip e  University of Rijeka, Croatia((.   Libertarianism&  Liberatirans see themselves as defenders of a notion of freedom that is incompatible with determinism and usually embrace the idea that the agent should be able to act and act otherwise given the same past circumstances and laws of nature. [Kane 2005] Only by being able to act otherwise we can say that we posses free will and therefore we can be held responsible for our actions. Restrictive libertarianism - we can do otherwise only on rare occasions, perhaps even extremely rare occasions. :P uW     T  Compatibilism  && pCompatibilists believe that determinism and the freedom of the will are compatible. We are free to do what we want to do as long as we can do what we want to do. If we have a good reason to act as we act and if there are no constraints or impediments preventing us from doing what we want to do  we are free. 9P9V6   Conditional analysis $$  BDoing otherwise? It is open to the compatibilist to say that human beings are very often  hundreds of times every day  able to do otherwise. [Van Inwagen 1989.] The conditional analysis "can do otherwise": the ability to do otherwise is some kind of specific, hypothetical ability that we have: to do otherwise means that if we desired or wanted or have chosen to act otherwise then we would have acted otherwise.>PP.PPT#   d    + The consequence argument$  P0  complete state of the world at time t L  conjunction of the laws of nature P  any true proposition Np - p is true and no one has or ever had any choice about p ((P0 & L) P) Consequence of determinism ((P0 L) P) 1, N((P0 L) P) 2, Alpha NP0 premise, fixity of the past N(L P) 3, 4, Beta NL premise, fixity of the laws NP 5, 6, BetaPoP+G     -           The consequence argument$  If this argument is sound, then determinism entails that no one has or ever had any choice about anything. Since one part of  anything is what any given person does, this amounts to say that determinism entails that no one could ever have done otherwise. [Van Inwagen 1989] Rule Alpha: p implies Nq Rule Beta: (Np & N(pq)) implies Nq Everyone who is a libertarian and accepts rule beta should also accept that only on rare occasions we are able to exhibit free will. DP!"0              } ~The argument for restrictive indeterminism  character examples@@$F    zThe starting point - character examples: According to Daniel Dennet [1984] character examples should show us that we are never able to act otherwise then we in fact do, as we have no reasons to act in a contrary way because we would be opposing our own character which is, among other things, constituted by our reasons for acting in certain specific way. Examples: Getting money in order to torture someone Lying about someone s scholary work x)P<P PNPP)< N         !|The argument for restrictive indeterminism  indefensible acts??$F     If our act is an indefensible act then the following conditional is true (& similar to a neccesary truth): C If X regards A as an indefensible act, given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he has no way of getting further relevant information, and if he lacks any positive desire to do A, and if he sees no objection to not doing A (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then X is not going to do A. [Van Inwagen 1989] Changing the example yields different results.Xkr/[NY\G  4 c ) 2 . A     The argument for restrictive indeterminism  using Beta from CQAAA&N   Beta prime: From N x,p and N x,(pq) deduce N x,q  N x,p is a two place operator that can be read as  p and x now has no choice about whether p . From here we can formulate the following argument: (1) N I, I regard A as indefensible (2) N I, (I regard A as indefensible I am not going to do A) (3) N I, I am not going to do A\ P'P!:             :  "nThe argument for restrictive indeterminism  conclusion88&4     & the general lesson is: if I regard a certain act as indefensible, then it follows not only that I shell not perform that act but that I can t perform it. [Van Inwagen 1989.] Non-open futures: futures to which someone cannot gain access to. &  L *The argument for restrictive indeterminism++&"   H(1) If the rule Beta-prime is valid, I cannot perform an act I regard as indefensible (2) If the rule Beta is valid, the rule Beta-prime is valid. (3) Free will is incompatible with determinism only if Beta is valid, hence (4) If free will is incompatible with determinism, then I cannot perform an act I regard as indefensible.II I The argument for restrictive indeterminism  unnopposed inclinationDD$F     A case of unopposed inclination: (1) At the moment the phone rings Mr. Nightingale does not have any choice about the fact that he very much desires to answer the phone. (2) He has no choice about its being the case that if he very much desires to answer the phone, then he is going to answer it. Therefore, (3) At the moment the phone rings, Mr. Nightingale is going to answer it and he has no choice about this. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.]"   d     #The argument for restrictive indeterminism  unreflective actionAA&F    A case of unreflective actions, normal everyday actions: (1) At the moment the phone rings, the person has no choice about the fact that he has no reason not to answer the phone immediately or to deliberate about answering it. (2) Furthermore, he has no choice about it being the case that if he hasn t any reason not to answer the phone then he is going to answer it. Therefore, (3) At the moment the phone rings, the agent is going to answer it and he has no choice about this. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] $Pz      ;Fischer and Ravizza against restrictive incompatibilism (1)<< H      [Van Inwagen maintains that the second premise of his argument is true: X has no choice about its being the case that, if he desires to answer the phone, then he is going to answer it. because the conditional C is a necessary truth: C If X regards A as an indefensible act, given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he has no way of getting further relevant information, and if he lacks any positive desire to do A, and if he sees no objection to not doing A (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then X is not going to do A. [Van Inwagen 1989.]fGro0osGr0s  #  ' B    $;Fischer and Ravizza against restrictive incompatibilism (2)<< H      When conditional C is applied in the argument regarding unopposed inclination Fischer and Ravizza reformulate it as follows: C2 If X very much desires to do some act A given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he lacks any positive desire to perform any act other then A, and if he sees no objection to doing A and refraining from doing anything else (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then the person is not going to do anything other then A. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] Fisher and Ravizza claim that C2 does not support the second premise of the argument or it does support the argument but it is not plausible. ,P}  ,         %F&R against restrictive incompatibilism (3)  C2 is plausible but non supportiveQQ p      C2 is founded on a conceptual truth: it is impossible for an agent to perform an action without having the desire to do so therfore C2 should read: C2* It is not possible that the following state of affair obtain: that C perform an act other then A without having any desire to perform such act. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] C2* fails to imply (2): X has no choice about its being the case that, if he desires to answer the phone, then he is going to answer it. Because X could have a unopposed desire but he could refrain from doing A. ZPqoPKoPPq/d{     ' A   ,!F&R against restrictive incompatibilism (3)  C2 is plausible but non supportiveQQ p      How? Because if there is no obstacle in having a desire to do something other then A:  (2) would be false if despite the fact that X has an unopposed desire to do A, he could refrain from doing A; and, given that (during the relevant time period) X can acquire this sort of desire, we believe that it is reasonable to suppose that X can do other then A A similar conclusion by F&R is drawn later on:  & even if an agent does not actually desire to do other then A, he might well have the ability (during the relevant temporal interval) to generate such a desire, and to act on this desire. And it is extremely implausible to suppose that agents quite generally lack the power to generate the relevant sort of desires. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.]WP P/PXP 2t/ J/S  E  & \   -#F&R against restrictive incompatibilism (3)  C2 is plausible but non supportiveQQ p      HWhy? C2* It is not possible that the following state of affair obtain: that C perform an act other then A without having any desire to perform such act. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] fails to imply (2): X has no choice about its being the case that, if he desires to answer the phone, then he is going to answer it. if this analogy is true:  it is not possible that the following state of affairs obtain at all points in some temporal interval: Jones is sitting and Jones is standing up. But this conceptual truth does not imply that, if Jones is sitting at some point in some temporal interval, then Jones cannot stand at some point in that interval. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.]ProPPRP rt    ' B ]    Against Fischer and Ravizza    .   Fischer s and Ravizza s analysis fails because they are adopting a strategy very similar to the hypothetical analysis of the notion  can do otherwise used by compatibilist in the debate regarding the consequence argument. If we change the motivational system of the agent, as Fischer and Ravizza do, then we are no longer talking about the same instance of deliberation. wwn      2 D  M &Against Fischer and Ravizza    .   Consider the following claim:  The leading idea here is that there is no reason to suppose that agents generally lack the power to generate (in some way or another) reasons to do otherwise, the power to try to act on those reasons, or the power to succeed is so acting. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] If there is some observable change in the way things are, this change must entail some change in the state of the world. The concept of 'state of the world' must be held fixed, speaking of general powers is not what we are dealing with in here  we are dealing with what happens in an exact situation.^P P.Pn     k   A note on responsibility   Derived responsibility:  What these examples [like drunk driving] show is that the inability to prevent or to refrain from causing a state of affairs does not logically preclude being to blame for that state of affairs. & while we are hardly ever able to act otherwise then we do, we are nevertheless accountable for (some of) the consequences of all of our acts. [Van Inwagen 1989.] Ultimate responsibility:  & to be "ultimately responsible" is to be an ultimate cause, or causal influence - one whose operation or influence is not caused or explained by anything else. & they were caused by us, and their occurring rather than not occurring then and there, had as its ultimate or final explanation the fact that they were caused by us then and there. [Kane 1989]PNr     CHow many choices? Van Inwagen: not too many! Classes of choices (1)DD ^    JThree classes of choices:  Buridan Ass cases Duty vs. inclination cases Cases of extreme importance:  Buridan Ass cases: the alternatives are interchangeable and the reason why someone doesn t know why to pick one heap of straw or the other is based exactly on that  interchangeability.  vanilla/chocolate situations - the alternatives aren t interchangeable but the chooser doesn t know which ice cream he wants. PL -PP -PPPM          + 'CHow many choices? Van Inwagen: not too many! Classes of choices (2)DD ^     Duty vs. inclination cases: Situations in which duty or general policy conflict with inclinations or momentary desires. These can be situations of moral struggle as one in which a young official is presented with a bribe and he is wavering on what to do. Cases of extreme importance:  The general form of the question that confronts the agent in true cases of the third type is, What sort of human being shell I be?, or What sort of life shell I live? & These cases are characterized by indecision, often agonized indecision. >PPPP  -Free choices: where should we draw the line?  .,  x Van Inwagen: - Buridan s Ass cases are not genuine instances of choosing. Phenomenologically speaking we are doing an internal coin toss, therefore we should conclude that we are not choosing anything. - For all incompatibilist who accept rule Beta, the only instances of free choices will be the ones in which the agent is presented either with a life choice between incommensurable values or choices in which the agent chooses between his duty or general policy and an inclination or momentary desire. *P/ -P     2  .  <    (-Free choices: where should we draw the line?  .,  x PWhy is it so? By discrediting the compatibilistic standard, in which almost every action we do can count as free, the libertarian went to look for a  freedom worth wanting , one that s worth wanting over and above compatibilist standard. A freedom which will give the agent "the power to be an ultimate creator and sustainer of one's own ends or purposes." [Kane 1994.] Do we really have to reject the Buridan s Ass cases?P|#  3  n        Weakness of the will   :  Self confidence is of enormous importance for us and sometimes situations of little relevance in outcome, the so called vanilla/chocolate cases become important not because of the flavor of ice cream that we will choose but rather they ll be relevant because we forced ourselves to make a choice  we forced ourselves out of idleness. Perhaps we can rephrase the following statement: We play to fight the idea of losing [Eric Cantona] in the following: We decide to fight the idea of losing (our self-confidence) LP3PP<PP     0  Irrelevant free choices?   B  Consider the following conditional when talking about indefensible acts: C If X regards A as an indefensible act, given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he has no way of getting further relevant information, and if he lacks any positive desire to do A, and if he sees no objection to not doing A (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then X is not going to do A. [Van Inwagen 1989]|IPr$!N*   d   )Irrelevant free choices?   B  yConsider the conditional used while talking about unopposed inclination: C2 If X very much desires to do some act A given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he lacks any positive desire to perform any act other then A, and if he sees no objection to doing A and refraining from doing anything else (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then the person is not going to do anything other then A. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] Van Inwagen assumes is that our everyday experience consists mostly of cases of decision making where our inclination towards one outcome is unopposed. :IP1?f      Lowering the standards   :  In the vacillation cases, if we have some reasons for both alternatives, but the importance of the outcome isn t too important for us then basically the decision we do seems like an internal coin toss, because the stakes are low. But is that decision unfree? P&   *Lowering the standards   :  +Why should we waste our precious resources, our time, our energy, our selfconfidence? Why should we frustrate ourselves or be under stress for such an act of minor relevance? There is no need for that. The amount of effort that we implement in our decision making will be higher if the stakes are higher and then we will get to the same level of invested energy and time as we do when we perform duty vs. inclination choices or choices of extreme importance. The only distinction a libertarian should adopt is the one between free and unfree decisions.,Z,@F       Theory / number of choices ratio!! L ~The number of free choices done per day is theory dependent: Hard incompatibilism - none Restrictive incompatibilism & (perhaps) libertarians adopting ultimate responsibiliy - on very rare occasions: (1) situations in which duty or general policy conflict with inclinations or momentary desires and (2) situations of extreme importance for the chooser when he is facing existential choices. Non-restrictive incompatibilists: - quite often: (1) situations in which duty or general policy conflict with inclinations or momentary desires and (2) situations of extreme importance for the chooser when he is facing existential choices. (3) Buridan Ass cases interpreted as cases of weakness of the will (4) Irrelevant free choices with competing reasons. Compatibilism - very often  perhaps hundreds of times every day@P@B    ,       n   7 o  0` j\Vtff3Ÿ` fBff33` .6aR3fi` 3fff` 3fff̙` fff33` f` 3'\m3fff` 33Ţ>?" dd@,?oFd(@ nK<)oAd=nKko2 n?" dd@   @@``PT   = ` `6p>>   ` F (    < "P `   T Click to edit Master title style! !$  0 " `  RClick to edit Master text styles Second level Third level Fourth level Fifth level!     S  0x "` @  >*   0 "`   @*   0| "``  @* T `P  "`PhB B s *D1" PP   <˜1"`,$D 0 20   <(Ș1"`~,$D 0 20   < ̘1"~H,$D 0 20   <Ϙ1"G,$D 0 20B  s *޽h ? .6aR3fi___PPT10i. a+D=' n= @B + Quadrant  W 0   p (    <1"p  20  <|r "`p r T Click to edit Master title style! !  0 "D T r W#Click to edit Master subtitle style$ $  0t "` `  >*   0t "`  t @*   0pt "` ` t B* T   "   B1"t 20   <ty1"| 20   By1"|p 20   <Dy1"zp 20hB  B s *D1"  B y1" 20B  s *޽h ? .6aR3fi___PPT10i. a+D=' n= @B +X 0N0  0(  x  c $y`p y x  c $yD T y H  0޽h ? 33___PPT10i.P;!+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 0(  x  c $$XyP `   y x  c $ ` y H  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.Ѽ+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 0(  x  c $8yP `   y x  c $tIy ` y H  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i. %V+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 <(  ~  s *yP `   y ~  s *Ԕy ` y H  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i. %V+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 `L(  ~  s *`NP `   N   s *LfN ` N yH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 0(  x  c $|yP `   y x  c $y ` y H  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0  <(  ~  s *yP `   y ~  s * y ` y H  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 <(  ~  s *@yP `   y ~  s *y ` y H  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 0R(  ~  s *зtP `   t   s *4t ` t "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *h#P `      s *xb `  "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 @R(  ~  s *$ %P `   %   s *y ` y "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 PL(  ~  s * %P `   %   c $`%T % "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 L(  ~  s *GP `   G   c $GT G "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 `R(  ~  s *$%P `   %   s *.% ` % "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *GP `   G   s *ؕG ` G "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *IP `   I   s *ԥ ` I "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 pR(  ~  s *PP `      s *vb `  "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 $R(  $~ $ s *LAnP `   n  $ s *Gr ` n "p`PpH $ 0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *d%P `   %   s *|j% ` % "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *IP `   I   s *Ȍ ` I "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *$r%P `   %   s *% ` % "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *4%P `   %   s *% ` % "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *,IP `   I   s *I ` I "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *d%P `   %   s *% ` % "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0  R(  ~  s *,GP `   G   s *r ` G "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *%P `   %   s *l% ` % "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *L%P `   %   s *H% ` % "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 0 R(   ~   s *x2NP `   N    s *(I ` N "p`PpH   0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *T%P `   %   s *ht ` % "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 PR(  ~  s *,NP `   N   s *iN ` N "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B + W 0N0 R(  ~  s *H&'gF  &   s *%j9 & "p`PpH  0޽h ? fff̙___PPT10i.pI+D=' n= @B +r0<P|^U fA) Cg2s L-1( F/ 0|DArialasRomanPP,EؖO 0ؖ"DTimes New RomanPP,EؖO 0ؖOh+'0* hp   , 8DL<Doxastic voluntarism and the libertarian notion of freedom Filip e Quadrant Filip e24Microsoft Office PowerPoint@Oު@#@0T+ G(g  W&vWMFCTTlx EMFT @@ F(GDICx!b $$=='.6% % V0xx x % % $$AA" FGDICF(GDICk( !b $$=='aR% % V0kccxxc% % $$AA" FGDICF(GDICl.vFGDICF(GDIC6ljvFGDICF(GDIClF(GDIC!b $$==% % V0  N N N% % $$AA: $$==_888 % % V,  N N % % $$AA( : " FGDICF(GDIC( !b $$=='i% % V0 cNc  NcN% % $$AA: $$==_888 % % V,ccN N % % $$AA( : " FGDICF(GDIC ( !b $$=='aR% % V0 cc  c% % $$AA: $$==_888 % % V,cc  % % $$AA( : " FGDICF(GDIC ( !b $$=='i% % V0      % % $$AA: $$==_888 % % V,  % % $$AA( : " FGDICF(GDIC >@!b $$==_888% % W$ <@8 % % $$AA( " FGDICF(GDICl!b : $$==_888 % % V,wcNc  N% % $$AA( : " FGDICFGDICF(GDIC =FGDICRp@Times New Roman|ژۘ L 0ۘ `Չ0504Ԙۘ0 \ޘPߘdv%    T,AA*L|How many choices can a    % ( Rp@Times New Roman|ژ܉Times y@Times 0 Ht hO00Ә504Ԙ tt%0`% Ć0\ޘߘdv%    T,a:AA8Lplibertarian make?  % ( F(GDIC AgFGDICRp@Arial|ژ܉Arialy@Arial 0 (t hO00Ә504Ԙ ptt% 0`% Ć0\ޘdv%    TpCHAAHLXFilip  % ( Rp@Arial|ژ@Arial 0 (t|@̆A|H]| :HH4Ԙ ptt% 0`%50Ԙ0 \ޘdv%p^Zw|%p  !Mdv%    TTCHAAHLP  % ( Rp@Arial|ژA|H]| :HH4Ԙ p|@̆A|H]| ;HHԘ0 \ޘdv%p^Zw|50t՘  !Mdv%p^Zw%p  !Mdv%    TTCHAAHLPe % ( Rp@Arial|ژA|H]| ;HHԘ0 \ޘ|@̆A|H]| >--'-- $jj--'@Times New Roman?-. *2 *How many choices can a   ."System-@Times New Roman?-. !2 8libertarian make?c .-@Arial?-. 2 HFilip .-@Arial?-.  2 HC.-@Arial?-.  2 He.-@Arial?-.  2 H c.-@ArialD?-. 32 PUniversity of Rijeka, Croatia.-!_2 Filip eFilip e     MOn-screen ShowV' %ArialTimes New Roman WingdingsSymbolVerdana Quadrant)How many choices can a libertarian make?LibertarianismCompatibilismConditional analysisRoot EntrydO)9̪ @Current User ;SummaryInformation(D*PowerPoint Document(V    !_2 Filip CecFilip Cec    MOn-screen ShowV' %ArialTimes New Roman WingdingsSymbolVerdana Quadrant)How many choices can a libertarian make?LibertarianismCompatibilismConditional analysis!_ Filip eFilip e   !"#$%&'()*+,-./0123456789:;<=>?@ABCDEFGHIJKLMNOPQRSTUVWXYZ[\]^_`abcdefghijklmnopqrstuvwxyz{|}~Root EntrydO) ?@>>   21   () 5    ()v wyz{|}~ 0AA@8WX:m ʚ;6_v8ʚ;g4PdPd O 0ppp@ <4ddddv 0PE<4!d!dv 0PE f0___PPT10 pp&___PPT9  * , #, ?  %(How many choices can a libertarian make? ) NFilip e  University of Rijeka, Croatia((.   Libertarianism&  Liberatirans see themselves as defenders of a notion of freedom that is incompatible with determinism and usually embrace the idea that the agent should be able to act and act otherwise given the same past circumstances and laws of nature. [Kane 2005] Only by being able to act otherwise we can say that we posses free will and therefore we can be held responsible for our actions. Restrictive libertarianism - we can do otherwise only on rare occasions, perhaps even extremely rare occasions. :P uW     T  Compatibilism  && pCompatibilists believe that determinism and the freedom of the will are compatible. We are free to do what we want to do as long as we can do what we want to do. If we have a good reason to act as we act and if there are no constraints or impediments preventing us from doing what we want to do  we are free. 9P9V6   Conditional analysis $$  BDoing otherwise? It is open to the compatibilist to say that human beings are very often  hundreds of times every day  able to do otherwise. [Van Inwagen 1989.] The conditional analysis "can do otherwise": the ability to do otherwise is some kind of specific, hypothetical ability that we have: to do otherwise means that if we desired or wanted or have chosen to act otherwise then we would have acted otherwise.>PP.PPT#   d    + The consequence argument$  P0  complete state of the world at time t L  conjunction of the laws of nature P  any true proposition Np - p is true and no one has or ever had any choice about p ((P0 & L) P) Consequence of determinism ((P0 L) P) 1, N((P0 L) P) 2, Alpha NP0 premise, fixity of the past N(L P) 3, 4, Beta NL premise, fixity of the laws NP 5, 6, BetaPoP+G     -           The consequence argument$  If this argument is sound, then determinism entails that no one has or ever had any choice about anything. Since one part of  anything is what any given person does, this amounts to say that determinism entails that no one could ever have done otherwise. [Van Inwagen 1989] Rule Alpha: p implies Nq Rule Beta: (Np & N(pq)) implies Nq Everyone who is a libertarian and accepts rule beta should also accept that only on rare occasions we are able to exhibit free will. DP!"0              } ~The argument for restrictive indeterminism  character examples@@$F    zThe starting point - character examples: According to Daniel Dennet [1984] character examples should show us that we are never able to act otherwise then we in fact do, as we have no reasons to act in a contrary way because we would be opposing our own character which is, among other things, constituted by our reasons for acting in certain specific way. Examples: Getting money in order to torture someone Lying about someone s scholary work x)P<P PNPP)< N         !|The argument for restrictive indeterminism  indefensible acts??$F     If our act is an indefensible act then the following conditional is true (& similar to a neccesary truth): C If X regards A as an indefensible act, given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he has no way of getting further relevant information, and if he lacks any positive desire to do A, and if he sees no objection to not doing A (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then X is not going to do A. [Van Inwagen 1989] Changing the example yields different results.Xkr/[NY\G  4 c ) 2 . A     The argument for restrictive indeterminism  using Beta from CQAAA&N   Beta prime: From N x,p and N x,(pq) deduce N x,q  N x,p is a two place operator that can be read as  p and x now has no choice about whether p . From here we can formulate the following argument: (1) N I, I regard A as indefensible (2) N I, (I regard A as indefensible I am not going to do A) (3) N I, I am not going to do A\ P'P!:             :  "nThe argument for restrictive indeterminism  conclusion88&4     & the general lesson is: if I regard a certain act as indefensible, then it follows not only that I shell not perform that act but that I can t perform it. [Van Inwagen 1989.] Non-open futures: futures to which someone cannot gain access to. &  L *The argument for restrictive indeterminism++&"   H(1) If the rule Beta-prime is valid, I cannot perform an act I regard as indefensible (2) If the rule Beta is valid, the rule Beta-prime is valid. (3) Free will is incompatible with determinism only if Beta is valid, hence (4) If free will is incompatible with determinism, then I cannot perform an act I regard as indefensible.II I The argument for restrictive indeterminism  unnopposed inclinationDD$F     A case of unopposed inclination: (1) At the moment the phone rings Mr. Nightingale does not have any choice about the fact that he very much desires to answer the phone. (2) He has no choice about its being the case that if he very much desires to answer the phone, then he is going to answer it. Therefore, (3) At the moment the phone rings, Mr. Nightingale is going to answer it and he has no choice about this. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.]"   d     #The argument for restrictive indeterminism  unreflective actionAA&F    A case of unreflective actions, normal everyday actions: (1) At the moment the phone rings, the person has no choice about the fact that he has no reason not to answer the phone immediately or to deliberate about answering it. (2) Furthermore, he has no choice about it being the case that if he hasn t any reason not to answer the phone then he is going to answer it. Therefore, (3) At the moment the phone rings, the agent is going to answer it and he has no choice about this. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] $Pz      ;Fischer and Ravizza against restrictive incompatibilism (1)<< H      [Van Inwagen maintains that the second premise of his argument is true: X has no choice about its being the case that, if he desires to answer the phone, then he is going to answer it. because the conditional C is a necessary truth: C If X regards A as an indefensible act, given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he has no way of getting further relevant information, and if he lacks any positive desire to do A, and if he sees no objection to not doing A (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then X is not going to do A. [Van Inwagen 1989.]fGro0osGr0s  #  ' B    $;Fischer and Ravizza against restrictive incompatibilism (2)<< H      When conditional C is applied in the argument regarding unopposed inclination Fischer and Ravizza reformulate it as follows: C2 If X very much desires to do some act A given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he lacks any positive desire to perform any act other then A, and if he sees no objection to doing A and refraining from doing anything else (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then the person is not going to do anything other then A. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] Fisher and Ravizza claim that C2 does not support the second premise of the argument or it does support the argument but it is not plausible. ,P}  ,         %F&R against restrictive incompatibilism (3)  C2 is plausible but non supportiveQQ p      C2 is founded on a conceptual truth: it is impossible for an agent to perform an action without having the desire to do so therfore C2 should read: C2* It is not possible that the following state of affair obtain: that C perform an act other then A without having any desire to perform such act. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] C2* fails to imply (2): X has no choice about its being the case that, if he desires to answer the phone, then he is going to answer it. Because X could have a unopposed desire but he could refrain from doing A. ZPqoPKoPPq/d{     ' A   ,!F&R against restrictive incompatibilism (3)  C2 is plausible but non supportiveQQ p      How? Because if there is no obstacle in having a desire to do something other then A:  (2) would be false if despite the fact that X has an unopposed desire to do A, he could refrain from doing A; and, given that (during the relevant time period) X can acquire this sort of desire, we believe that it is reasonable to suppose that X can do other then A A similar conclusion by F&R is drawn later on:  & even if an agent does not actually desire to do other then A, he might well have the ability (during the relevant temporal interval) to generate such a desire, and to act on this desire. And it is extremely implausible to suppose that agents quite generally lack the power to generate the relevant sort of desires. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.]WP P/PXP 2t/ J/S  E  & \   -#F&R against restrictive incompatibilism (3)  C2 is plausible but non supportiveQQ p      HWhy? C2* It is not possible that the following state of affair obtain: that C perform an act other then A without having any desire to perform such act. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] fails to imply (2): X has no choice about its being the case that, if he desires to answer the phone, then he is going to answer it. if this analogy is true:  it is not possible that the following state of affairs obtain at all points in some temporal interval: Jones is sitting and Jones is standing up. But this conceptual truth does not imply that, if Jones is sitting at some point in some temporal interval, then Jones cannot stand at some point in that interval. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.]ProPPRP rt    ' B ]    Against Fischer and Ravizza    .   Fischer s and Ravizza s analysis fails because they are adopting a strategy very similar to the hypothetical analysis of the notion  can do otherwise used by compatibilist in the debate regarding the consequence argument. If we change the motivational system of the agent, as Fischer and Ravizza do, then we are no longer talking about the same instance of deliberation. wwn      2 D  M &Against Fischer and Ravizza    .   Consider the following claim:  The leading idea here is that there is no reason to suppose that agents generally lack the power to generate (in some way or another) reasons to do otherwise, the power to try to act on those reasons, or the power to succeed is so acting. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] If there is some observable change in the way things are, this change must entail some change in the state of the world. The concept of 'state of the world' must be held fixed, speaking of general powers is not what we are dealing with in here  we are dealing with what happens in an exact situation.^P P.Pn     k   A note on responsibility   Derived responsibility:  What these examples [like drunk driving] show is that the inability to prevent or to refrain from causing a state of affairs does not logically preclude being to blame for that state of affairs. & while we are hardly ever able to act otherwise then we do, we are nevertheless accountable for (some of) the consequences of all of our acts. [Van Inwagen 1989.] Ultimate responsibility:  & to be "ultimately responsible" is to be an ultimate cause, or causal influence - one whose operation or influence is not caused or explained by anything else. & they were caused by us, and their occurring rather than not occurring then and there, had as its ultimate or final explanation the fact that they were caused by us then and there. [Kane 1989]PNr     CHow many choices? Van Inwagen: not too many! Classes of choices (1)DD ^    JThree classes of choices:  Buridan Ass cases Duty vs. inclination cases Cases of extreme importance:  Buridan Ass cases: the alternatives are interchangeable and the reason why someone doesn t know why to pick one heap of straw or the other is based exactly on that  interchangeability.  vanilla/chocolate situations - the alternatives aren t interchangeable but the chooser doesn t know which ice cream he wants. PL -PP -PPPM          + 'CHow many choices? Van Inwagen: not too many! Classes of choices (2)DD ^     Duty vs. inclination cases: Situations in which duty or general policy conflict with inclinations or momentary desires. These can be situations of moral struggle as one in which a young official is presented with a bribe and he is wavering on what to do. Cases of extreme importance:  The general form of the question that confronts the agent in true cases of the third type is, What sort of human being shell I be?, or What sort of life shell I live? & These cases are characterized by indecision, often agonized indecision. >PPPP  -Free choices: where should we draw the line?  .,  x Van Inwagen: - Buridan s Ass cases are not genuine instances of choosing. Phenomenologically speaking we are doing an internal coin toss, therefore we should conclude that we are not choosing anything. - For all incompatibilist who accept rule Beta, the only instances of free choices will be the ones in which the agent is presented either with a life choice between incommensurable values or choices in which the agent chooses between his duty or general policy and an inclination or momentary desire. *P/ -P     2  .  <    (-Free choices: where should we draw the line?  .,  x PWhy is it so? By discrediting the compatibilistic standard, in which almost every action we do can count as free, the libertarian went to look for a  freedom worth wanting , one that s worth wanting over and above compatibilist standard. A freedom which will give the agent "the power to be an ultimate creator and sustainer of one's own ends or purposes." [Kane 1994.] Do we really have to reject the Buridan s Ass cases?P|#  3  n        Weakness of the will   :  Self confidence is of enormous importance for us and sometimes situations of little relevance in outcome, the so called vanilla/chocolate cases become important not because of the flavor of ice cream that we will choose but rather they ll be relevant because we forced ourselves to make a choice  we forced ourselves out of idleness. Perhaps we can rephrase the following statement: We play to fight the idea of losing [Eric Cantona] in the following: We decide to fight the idea of losing (our self-confidence) LP3PP<PP     0  Irrelevant free choices?      B  Consider the following conditional when talking about indefensible acts: C If X regards A as an indefensible act, given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he has no way of getting further relevant information, and if he lacks any positive desire to do A, and if he sees no objection to not doing A (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then X is not going to do A. [Van Inwagen 1989]|IPr$!N*   d   )Irrelevant free choices?   B  yConsider the conditional used while talking about unopposed inclination: C2 If X very much desires to do some act A given the totality of relevant information available to him, and if he lacks any positive desire to perform any act other then A, and if he sees no objection to doing A and refraining from doing anything else (again, given the totality of relevant information available to him), then the person is not going to do anything other then A. [Fischer / Ravizza 1992.] Van Inwagen assumes is that our everyday experience consists mostly of cases of decision making where our inclination towards one outcome is unopposed. :IP1?f      Lowering the standards   :  In the vacillation cases, if we have some reasons for both alternatives, but the importance of the outcome isn t too important for us then basically the decision we do seems like an internal coin toss, because the stakes are low. But is that decision unfree? P&   *Lowering the standards   :  +Why should we waste our precious resources, our time, our energy, our selfconfidence? Why should we frustrate ourselves or be under stress for such an act of minor relevance? There is no need for that. The amount of effort that we implement in our decision making will be higher if the stakes are higher and then we will get to the same level of invested energy and time as we do when we perform duty vs. inclination choices or choices of extreme importance. The only distinction a libertarian should adopt is the one between free and unfree decisions.,Z,@F       Theory / number of choices ratio!! L ~The number of free choices done per day is theory dependent: Hard incompatibilism - none Restrictive incompatibilism & (perhaps) libertarians adopting ultimate responsibiliy - on very rare occasions: (1) situations in which duty or general policy conflict with inclinations or momentary desires and (2) situations of extreme importance for the chooser when he is facing existential choices. Non-restrictive incompatibilists: - quite often: (1) situations in which duty or general policy conflict with inclinations or momentary desires and (2) situations of extreme importance for the chooser when he is facing existential choices. (3) Buridan Ass cases interpreted as cases of weakness of the will (4) Irrelevant free choices with competing reasons. Compatibilism - very often  perhaps hundreds of times every day@P@B    ,       n   7 rs "-1 ՜.+,0    MOn-screen ShowV' %ArialTimes New Roman WingdingsSymbolVerdana Quadrant)How many choices can a libertarian make?LibertarianismCompatibilismConditional analysisThe consequence argumentThe consequence argument@The argument for restrictive indeterminism character examples?The argument for restrictive indeterminism indefensible actsAThe argument for restrictive indeterminism using Beta from CQA8The argument for restrictive indeterminism conclusion+The argument for restrictive indeterminismDThe argument for restrictive indeterminism unnopposed inclinationAThe argument for restrictive indeterminism unreflective action<Fischer and Ravizza against restrictive incompatibilism (1)<Fischer and Ravizza against restrictive incompatibilism (2)QF&R against restrictive incompatibilism (3) C2 is plausible but non supportiveQF&R against restrictive incompatibilism (3) C2 is plausible but non supportiveQF&R against restrictive incompatibilism (3) C2 is plausible but non supportiveAgainst Fischer and Ravizza Against Fischer and Ravizza A note on responsibilityDHow many choices? Van Inwagen: not too many! Classes of choices (1)DHow many choices? Van Inwagen: not too many! Classes of choices (2).Free choices: where should we draw the line? .Free choices: where should we draw the line? Weakness of the willIrrelevant free choices?Irrelevant free choices?Lowering the standardsLowering the standards!Theory / number of choices ratio  Fonts UsedDesign Template Slide Titles